Death Penalty as a Deterrent for Murder Paper

Abstract

This paper examines the death penalty as a deterrent and argues that states have not only the right but the duty to apply the death penalty to criminal cases because it is incumbent upon states to back the law with force. The death penalty acts as a forceful and compelling consequence for those who should choose to violate the law and commit murder. For that reason it can be said to be a deterrent. This paper also examines the opposing arguments and shows that those would say it is not an effective deterrent cannot offer any quantitative proof for this argument because no measurements exist that could possibly render such a claim factual or provable. The paper concludes by showing that the death penalty should only be administered in states where there is harmony between social justice and criminal justice.

 

Introduction

While it may seem ironic that the death penalty should be considered as a deterrent for murder, the underlying premise that supports the proposition is simply this: laws must be backed by force in order to be compelling, and if the force is insufficient to carry the weight needed to compel order and respect for the law in society, both law and order will be unenforceable and therefore unsupportive of the natural aims of society. From this perspective, therefore, it may be seen that the death penalty carries no actual ironic tone in terms of acting as a deterrent for murder but rather that it acts as the necessary force of repercussion or consequence that a murderer can expect to experience should he violate the law which forbids the taking of life. In order to protect life, liberty and the pursuit of justice, the force of justice itself must be clear, palpable and discernible by those in society. If it is not, the moral compulsion to respect laws and follow them, including the law forbidding the killing of another person, will not be effective enough to deter persons from behaving badly. The moral order must be supported by the social order or else the social order itself will be undermined by its own lack of respect for moral law. Hammurabi in ancient times promoted this concept in his “eye for an eye” approach to law. The Old Testament mirrored this sentiment: “But if there is any further injury, then you shall appoint as a penalty life for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth, hand for hand, foot for foot, burn for burn, wound for wound, bruise for bruise” (Ex 21:23-25). Though the teachings of the New Testament have suggested to some that such a concept was abolished by the law of Christ—“You have heard that it was said, ‘Eye for eye and tooth for tooth.’ But I tell you not to resist an evil person. If someone slaps you on your right cheek, turn to him the other also” (Mat 5:38-39)—the reality is that this was not the only pronouncement that Christ made upon the subject of killing. Indeed, He also stated that “those who live by the sword will die by the sword” (Mat 26:52). One can see in this important reminder from the most central figure in the history of the world that actions must have consequences, and it is up to those who would uphold the law that this concept not be lost on the public. For that reason, this paper will show that the death penalty must act and does act as a deterrent for murder when it is effectively applied in a system of justice that is fairly and equitably distributed.

 

No Respect for Law: When Capital Punishment May NOT Act as a Deterrent

In a society where the system of justice is unequally distributed by the upholders of the law, the application of the death penalty as a deterrent for murder cannot be said to be effectively applied. This is why it is imperative that the system of justice and the rule of law itself be implicitly and explicitly respected and enforced fairly and equitably for the death penalty to serve as a deterrent for murder. Consequences for actions must be established clearly and consistently in order for them to carry weight, to be seen as meaningful, and to be expected as the social and personal outcome of individual decisions (Weaver, 1984). If legislation is passed that prohibits certain acts but the prohibition of these acts is only executed sloppily or at best inconsistently, whatever deterrents might be utilized as consequences for breaking the law will be scorned by the general public. Indeed, history offers a perfect example of this principle with the Era of Prohibition in the U.S. during the 1920s when alcohol was outlawed and scofflaws (so-named because they scoffed at a law that was both despised by the public and ineffectively enforced by law enforcement officers). Individuals violated the laws of prohibition routinely by way of speakeasies, subversion of the legalistic parameters of the law (which allowed one to imbibe alcohol with a doctor’s note—similar to the way in which medicinal marijuana laws today allow one to legally escape prosecution under federal law for imbibing a schedule one narcotic), and other criminal activity. The end result of the lack of a true deterrent being able to be applied (mainly because of the lack of moral justification for the law in the first place) was that the social order became worse after than it was before: the rise of organized crime was ushered into existence thanks to the Era of Prohibition, and it has not gone away to this day (Bursik, 1988). In order for the death penalty to serve as a deterrent for murder, it must therefore be applied in a system of law that is moral, consistent, equitable and fair. If that system is pervaded by other unjust laws, is inconsistently applied with regard to fairness and equitability, or is riddled with corruption (“the law’s delay” and the “insolence of office” as Shakespeare put it in Hamlet), the application of the death penalty as a deterrent cannot be justified simply because the law itself is ineptly executed and justice is unfairly served. In order for capital punishment to deter, law and order must already exist. In a society where neither can be said to exist, capital punishment serves no purpose other than to excuse a system of tyranny in a social system that has abandoned the need for moral justifications.

 

The law itself must be in accordance with morality or moral law. If it is judged to be opposed to the moral order that is innate in mankind, the social law will be rejected and spurned and the consequences of breaking it will also be despised (Bazelon, 1975). In other words, if the law is immoral, no so-called deterrent will effectively act as such because the law itself will not support a moral justification for such repercussions. Pretending as though they do is the perfect way to introduce the concept of martyrdom into the public arena once more. For instance, a martyr is one who is unjustly made to suffer (usually by way of execution) for violating a law (the consequence of which is death) that is unjustifiable in a moral society. Criminal justice and social justice must be in accordance, as Bazelon (1975) asserts, in order for a system of law to work, to be fair, to be equitable, and to be effective. In a society where social justice is at odds with criminal justice, the death penalty may not be prescribed as a deterrent to murder because the two systems—social justice and criminal justice—are out of alignment. To propose a negative solution to a minor problem without actually addressing the real major problem would be like attempting to fix an engine whose rod bearing is disintegrating by changing the oil. The effect will be innocuous at best, dangerous at worst (especially if it is assumed that the deterrent will satisfactorily address the problem of murder). In such an environment where social justice and criminal justice are out of alignment, where the moral order is not supported by the legal order or framework, deterrents are more tyrannical than they are morally enforceable. This is why it is imperative that criminal justice and social justice be united within a system of law and order. Failure to unite makes the practice of justice impracticable.

 

In the American system of justice, there is a clear controversy as to the extent to which social justice and criminal justice are in harmony. In the speeches of Angela Y. Davis (2012), it can be seen that the African American community is deeply distrustful of the criminal justice system specifically and precisely because it has such a long history in the U.S. of being at odds with social justice where fairness and equitability are practiced without respect for race, creed or ethnicity. Unnever and Cullen (2007) support this perspective, noting that there are clear racial disparities in terms of the distribution of capital punishment. National statistics on the race of defendants executed in the U.S. since 1976 show that 34.5% of those executed were black (“National Statistics on the Death Penalty and Race,” 2018). Yet according to the 2010 Census, blacks only make up 12.6% of the U.S. population. This is nearly a 300% increase in representation—a shocking figure when one considers that whites make up 72.4% of the population according to the same Census, yet only account for 55.6% of all persons executed in the U.S. since 1976 under the death penalty—nearly a 20% decrease. If the ratio of whites executed under the death penalty to whites in the U.S. population is lower, why is exponentially higher for blacks? The answer is supplied by social justice activists like Davis (2012) who says that the criminal justice system in America represents the US Organization—a violently racist system of oppression designed to marginalize blacks and install them in a new system of slavery manifested in the rise of the prison-industrial complex. From her position, the criminal justice system is an “ideological campaign to persuade us once again…that race is a marker of criminality” (Davis, 2012, p. 38). So if criminal justice in America is blocked by racist ideology implementing a system of law and order that is in harmony with actual social justice, when is it appropriate to use the death penalty as a deterrent for murder?

 

When Social Justice and Criminal Justice are in Alignment: Deterrents are Necessary

The answer to that question is simple: when social justice and criminal justice are in harmony, the death penalty may be appropriately administered as a deterrent for murder. In this harmony, it is acknowledged by society that the criminal justice system, that the framework of law and order in the community, is moral and justifiable and can and should, therefore, be respected. Out of this respect comes the acknowledgement that the justice system has the capacity and obligation to exercise force in order to support its laws. A system of rule that does not possess the force of its own convictions is a rule that will not last long.

 

Are criminal justice and social justice ever truly in alignment? This question is far less easily answered. Over the course of human history, societies, cultures, communities and nations have evolved, as new ideas, new people, and new technology produce changes in the way people live, think and act. These changes are not always in harmony with the social or legal systems and frameworks in place from generations earlier, and thus it is difficult to assert that a true harmony ever really exists between society and the law, no matter the time or place. In some eras and in some regions of the world the harmony has been more pronounced than in others. However, it is undoubtedly the case that throughout time, many societies have been in some degree of opposition to the system of rules and laws institutionalized and practiced. This is especially true in the modern era, wherein revolution has played such an intricate role in the evolution of society. From the Protestant Reformation to the Scientific Revolution (out of which came the Enlightenment) to the American Revolution to the French Revolution to the Industrial Revolution to the Russian Revolution to the Cultural Revolution to our own Digital Revolution, nations have warred within themselves, indicating that peace between society and the institutions set up to govern society has been more ephemeral than concrete and harmonious.

 

In the medieval world, tensions also existed but these were far more localized with the power structure being monarchical and hierarchical rather than democratic as it is in many nations today. In the hierarchical settings, the death penalty was used, too—even in the Church of the Old World where confirmed heretics were condemned to death in cases where they refused to retract their views and insisted on spreading beliefs and ideas that the Church found to be mortally dangerous to the souls of the faithful. In the case of Joan of Arc, churchmen in the Church’s hierarchy in Rouen, France, even went so far as to burn at the stake a woman whom many of the faithful of the Church believed at the time (and whom the Church Herself would go on to believe) was a saint, viewing her death as a politically motivated by the English who resented her claims of divine assistance to the French during the Hundred Years’ War. In her case, one sees again the abuses that can take place in the justice system—no matter the place or time or era. Nonetheless, the case of Joan of Arc is an instance in which an abuse of a system of law and order by and large in harmony with the community’s culture and with the community’s sense of social justice. It is an example of the fact that abuses can occur—but not an example of an argument that the death penalty may not serve as a deterrent.

 

In societies where the sense of social justice is in accordance with the society’s system of rule and law, it is natural and effective that capital punishment should serve as a deterrent, as this penalty produces a forceful reminder to the community that actions do have consequences. It can be especially necessary in societies and communities where the rule of law needs to be firmly applied in order to quell the rebellious natures of persons within the community who are not in conformity with the values, beliefs and aims of that community. For instance, in the New World, public hangings have their own history as a form of death penalty used to punish capital offenders. Throughout American history, one can see how states have used hanging to emphasize the fact that murder was a crime that would not be tolerated. The Great Emancipator himself, Abraham Lincoln, allowed the execution by hanging of 39 Sioux who were convicted of murdering a group of settlers in Minnesota (Randa, 1997). The public execution was both shocking (purposefully so) and necessary from the standpoint of law and order—especially with an eye towards taming the Frontier and establishing justice in the “Wild West.” As a deterrent, the death penalty’s power, qualitatively speaking, is undeniable—though still argued by those who oppose its usage on moral, ethical or even pragmatic and utilitarian grounds: and these objectors are not a few.

 

Richard Wright famously opposed it in the 20th century with his novel Native Son, in which a young black man named Bigger Thomas irrationally murders a young white woman in her bedroom. He is arrested, tried, convicted and sentenced to death. He expresses no remorse for his actions but exhibits a kind of pathetic innocence in the sense that he is portrayed almost as a victim of the kind of racial oppression described by Davis in her speeches. He rejects the overtures of a priest. His lawyer attempts to persuade the jury that capital punishment is a perpetuation of the kind of crime that Thomas himself committed, a perpetuation of irrational inhumanity—when what is needed in the world is compassion, empathy, and mercy. The jury does not buy the argument and Thomas is executed. The argument of his lawyer, though, is Wright’s argument—and essentially the argument of every objector to the death penalty as a natural deterrent. The problem with it, though it is compelling in its own right, is that from a logical perspective, the death penalty is not a perpetuation of irrational inhumanity but a reinforcement of exactly the opposite: the sense that human beings should be guided by reason rather than emotion and impulse. This is not to suggest that Wright or Bigger Thomas’s lawyer is incorrect in arguing that what the world needs more of is compassion, empathy and mercy. But for the sake of justice and the rule of law, society also needs a show of force, and that show of force is exhibited in the death penalty. The only question that arises following the consent of this fact is whether or not the death penalty actually works as a deterrent.

 

Does Deterrence Work?

Does the death penalty “work” as a deterrent? Does it actually deter would-be murderers? This question is somewhat impossible to answer because no quantitative study can be performed to measure statistically whether a would-be murderer was prevented from murdering based on his or her awareness of the fact that there is a mortal consequence established by the state for committing the crime. Qualitatively speaking, the penalty’s deterrence factor can be felt. But feelings aside, one must examine the arguments of those who oppose it. Those who oppose it today—such as Michael Moore in his documentary on Norway’s prison system—point to other nations and modern cultures that have managed to address issues of crime without espousing a legal system in which capital punishment plays a part. And while these arguments may be effective in highlighting alternative views of justice, they in no way can or do invalidate the claim that the death penalty is a deterrent. Deterrence cannot be measured by any earthly means. It can only be asserted as a prerogative.

 

Even Rose (2011) writing for the National Defense University Joint Forces Staff College acknowledges that deterrence is impossible to measure while asserting that measures may be implemented to help gauge to a limited degree the effectiveness that a deterrent may be having. Rose (2011) writes:

 

The concept of deterrence is as old as war, but determining if deterrence activities and messages are having the desired effect on the adversary decision maker is challenging since the adversary will not readily admit to being deterred. Developing deterrence measures of effectiveness is imperative to determine if deterrence activities and messages are meeting the deterrence strategy objectives and achieving the desired end states. However, determining why something did not occur is difficult to assess (p. 1).

 

Those who argue, therefore, that the death penalty does not act as a deterrent or that it is an ineffective deterrent have no factual ground to stand on—only a flimsy moral claim whose premised is based on their personal dislike of killing; that—or, as has been stated earlier in this paper, their objection is based on the fact that there is no harmony between social justice and criminal justice; in which case their objection then has substantial merit for the fact that justice must be fair and equitable in order for it to be moral and morally supportable.

 

Assuming that there is harmony between a community’s sense of social justice and its system of criminal justice, governors have the prerogative to use the death penalty as a deterrent as befits their role as governors and guardians of the state. A parent who offers his children no discipline undermines his own authority. A state that provides its citizens with no disciplinary actions or repercussions for criminal behavior is a state that undermines its own authority. Deterrence is a prerogative that may be exercised by virtue of the fact that the law must be enforced or else it has no meaning. The death penalty may be viewed as a harsh example or demonstration of that force, but its moral justification is situated in the very concept of the rule of law. Without the force of demonstration, the law has no voice and no power to convict. Without the power to convict, the law is limp and useless.

 

That said, the West has been greatly influenced by the concept of the “rights of man,” notably propagated by Thomas Paine is his work of the same title. Essentially, this concept boils down to the idea that every man has rights that are his by nature and not by any human authority or hierarchy. This concept supported the vision of the Framers of the Constitution as they developed the Bill of Rights and the early Amendments, which focused in particularly on protecting the rights of the new citizens of the American Republic from tyrannical abuses committed by the State. In this sense, the Framers of the Constitution were attempting to devise a safeguard should social justice and criminal justice ever become disharmonious in the U.S. These rights designed, in other words, to prevent unfairness and inequitableness from creeping into the system of law and order. Over time, these rights have been interpreted and amended as well, and Supreme Court decisions have clarified their meaning, whether for better or for worse. The point is that none of this was done because of a dislike or antipathy towards the death penalty as a deterrent but rather as a way to ensure that justice was united to the moral framework of the nation’s forefathers.

 

With this in mind, and though one may be tempted to embrace the arguments of the social activists like Angela Davis, who condemn the criminal justice system as corrupted by racist and elitist doctrines, the reality is difficult to discern—as difficult to discern as is the measure of the effectiveness of deterrence in quantitative terms. Is America, for instance, capable of producing harmony between communities’ sense of social justice and communities’ criminal justice system? Is this harmony even capable of being measured? In a perfect world, perhaps so—but this world is far from being perfect, which is why the death penalty is needed as a deterrent in the first place.

 

Resolving the Issue

How then to resolve the issue of effecting a deterrent in a society where alignment between social justice and criminal justice is uncertain, where abuses are plentifully documented (one need only watch any series of films, from Making of a Murderer to The West Memphis Three to understand how local law enforcement can be as drastically misleading as the English were in Rouen in trial of Joan of Arc). Does this ambiguity or this evidence of corruption indicate that deterrent penalties like capital punishment should be removed from the books and set aside in favor of the kind of mercy, compassion and empathy advocated by Wright, Bigger Thomas’s lawyer, and advocate like Angela Davis? Of course, those qualities should always be promoted, but to put them in the place of the force of law is to supplant one prerogative with another. It is, in a sense, to advocate Matthew 5:38-39 over Exodus 21:23-25 or Matthew 26:52. The fact is that society must live with both of these perspectives and combine them within a system of justice. The social systems of the modern era are replete with revolutionary forces that take the revolution as a matter of faith. They believe in the revolution, in the constant overthrow of dysfunctional governments so that a better, fresher administration may have an opportunity to govern. This approach does not breed stability but rather instability. Instead of perennially looking forward, it may suffice to look backward and learn the old lessons of social order.

 

The clash between social consciousness and institutionalize authority in the modern era is not likely to dissipate any time soon. The powers of government, especially in the 21st century, have taken on dimensions that more and more resemble authoritarian regimes—the nightmare realities of men like Orwell who envisioned just such a state as ours in 1984. Surely there is no place for the death penalty as a deterrent force in such a world: the very fabric of law and order has been subverted, the moral order inverted, and the qualities of fairness and equitability banished from the human consciousness. The death penalty may not morally be used as a deterrent in such an environment because there is no framework for justice in the first place. How can an example of force be made to support a sense of justice when the very concept of justice is eradicated from the state’s system or framework? It cannot—and to the degree that it might be said that modern American society resembles Orwell’s 1984, the death penalty may need to be avoided—at least until some measure of fairness and equitability is restored and harmony between social justice and criminal justice is demonstrated, as Bazelon (1975) advocated.

 

However, to generalize on the subject is also to miss the trees for the forest. It should be considered that every case brought to trial is unique, and is full of unique persons, circumstances, situations and characteristics that are not and cannot be duplicated in another setting, in another place, at another point in time. The trial of Joan of Arc will not and never has been exactly replicated in any other trial in history, though there have been other trials in which saintly persons have been condemned to death (one thinks of the trial of Socrates, as described by Plato, for instance). In every individual case, therefore, it is the responsibility of the individual stakeholders in that case to make certain that justice is fair and equitable—that the rights of the accused are not violated and are in accordance with those provided by the system of law acknowledged and supported by society. Stakeholders may range from defendants to counsel to judges to juries to witnesses in the courtroom to protestors on the streets to journalists and academics. The law is there for society, to protect it, guide it, support it and nourish it. It is not there to cudgel, to tyrannize over, or to subjugate with.

 

Stakeholders who are committed to one another should also be committed to ensuring that the process of law is likewise committed to the communities for whom it is given. Their involvement in the execution of justice is necessitated. Their involvement should be mediated by their own desire to see that justice is fair and equitable—so that there is harmony and alignment between the community’s sense of social justice and its sense of criminal justice. And with that alignment comes the awareness that the rule of law must ultimately be backed by the force of its convictions—and that means that in cases where the accused is tried for murder the use of the death penalty as a punishment is appropriate should the accused be convicted. This is not to say that it must be applied but rather that the option should be available. Mercy, compassion and empathy are also options—and they have their own benefits, too. But in every case, it should be up to those involved in the execution of the law, in the pronouncement of judgments, to determine the sentencing.

 

For that reason, it is not in keeping with the concepts of fairness and equitability to assert blanket statements about where and in which cases the death penalty should and should not be applied. Its power as a deterrent can be felt by one and all by the force of sheer imagination—and that is what gives it such a shocking and controversial nature in the modern world. There is in it the brutal recognition that lives may become forfeit to the state should people choose to violate the laws of the state. The concern, however, that many have—people like Davis, for example—is that the state should not violate the moral laws that support and nourish the community and its values. Balancing the need for states to exist and govern appropriately and effectively with the need for communities to feel safe and protected from tyrannical abuses of the state was a top concern of America’s forefathers. That concern has not diminished with time and remains today though the voices that express it are different.

 

In the final analysis, the death penalty is a deterrent for murder by nature of its compelling forcefulness. The effectiveness of its deterrence quality may be debated, but that debate will never come to a satisfactory conclusion simply because such effectiveness cannot be measured here on earth. No one knows the true extent of its effectiveness. To oppose the concept of the death penalty as a deterrent, however, is to miss the actual reason that the state has a prerogative to apply the death penalty in the first place—and that reason is to provide a compelling force to the law so that its weight and gravity can be felt by those who live within its circumference. Whether or not the death penalty actual deters people from committing murder is, in a sense, beside the point. The fact is that the application of the death penalty as a deterrent is a sign of the value of life in the first place. One who would dare take another person’s life is one who must be ready to forfeit his own. A state that prohibits murder but that does not provide a compelling reason via negative consequence for the members of its community to follow the law is a state that will appear weak and inconsequential in its governance. It invites an aspect of the “Wild West” days and leaves open the possibility of marauders like the 39 Sioux who slaughtered settlers in Minnesota to enter in and wreak havoc. As Weaver (1984) points out, ideas have consequences and the idea of not having a deterrent for murder on the law books is one that could quickly lead to a rise in savagery, simply because of the culture that the modern era has festered. In a simpler age, where virtue and ethics were more normative and universal than they sometimes seem today, stakeholders in that community’s government may have found it possible to arrive at a different conclusion.

 

Conclusion

Even though it may appear ironic to those who oppose the death penalty, capital punishment as a deterrent for murder is a prerogative of the state to enforce its law. It is important, however, that the law is aligned with the values of society and that the moral order is represented in the state’s rule of law. If the state does not forcefully compel its citizens to take seriously its laws, it undermines its own position as a representative of authority. Actions must have consequences and it is the state’s duty towards its citizens to see to it that they do. The consequences of murder have been since the most ancient of times death for the murderer. Hammurabi said “an eye for an eye” and this sentiment is echoed in the Old Testament in the Book of Exodus. Christ offered a new focus for mankind, one rooted in mercy and forgiveness—but He also iterated the fact that those who kill will indeed be killed. In the modern era, it may be helpful for societies and states to remember temper the law with mercy and to reflect in judgments the needs expressed by activists like Davis and authors like Wright—needs that emphasize the importance of empathy and compassion. At the same time, the state must ensure that security and the force of the law are compelling—and for that reason the death penalty may serve as an appropriate deterrent.

 

References

Bazelon, D. L. (1975). The morality of the criminal law. Southern California Law Review, 49, 385-405.

 

Bursik, R. (1988). Social disorganization and theories of crime and delinquency: Problems and prospects. Criminology, 26(4): 519-552.

 

Davis, A. Y. (2012) The Meaning of Freedom. San Francisco, CA: City Light Books. National Statistics on the Death Penalty and Race. (2018). Retrieved from https://deathpenaltyinfo.org/race-death-row-inmates-executed-1976

 

Randa, L. (1997). Society’s final solution: A history and discussion of the death penalty. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

 

Rose, D. (2011). Only in the mind of the enemy: Can deterrence effectiveness be measured? National Defense University Joint Forces Staff College.

 

Weaver, R. (1984). Ideas have consequences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

 

Unnever, J., Cullen, F. (2007). Reassessing the Racial Divide in Support for Capital Punishment. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 44(1), 124-158.


Get Professional Assignment Help Cheaply

Buy Custom Essay

Are you busy and do not have time to handle your assignment? Are you scared that your paper will not make the grade? Do you have responsibilities that may hinder you from turning in your assignment on time? Are you tired and can barely handle your assignment? Are your grades inconsistent?

Whichever your reason is, it is valid! You can get professional academic help from our service at affordable rates. We have a team of professional academic writers who can handle all your assignments.

Why Choose Our Academic Writing Service?

  • Plagiarism free papers
  • Timely delivery
  • Any deadline
  • Skilled, Experienced Native English Writers
  • Subject-relevant academic writer
  • Adherence to paper instructions
  • Ability to tackle bulk assignments
  • Reasonable prices
  • 24/7 Customer Support
  • Get superb grades consistently
 

Online Academic Help With Different Subjects

Literature

Students barely have time to read. We got you! Have your literature essay or book review written without having the hassle of reading the book. You can get your literature paper custom-written for you by our literature specialists.

Finance

Do you struggle with finance? No need to torture yourself if finance is not your cup of tea. You can order your finance paper from our academic writing service and get 100% original work from competent finance experts.

Computer science

Computer science is a tough subject. Fortunately, our computer science experts are up to the match. No need to stress and have sleepless nights. Our academic writers will tackle all your computer science assignments and deliver them on time. Let us handle all your python, java, ruby, JavaScript, php , C+ assignments!

Psychology

While psychology may be an interesting subject, you may lack sufficient time to handle your assignments. Don’t despair; by using our academic writing service, you can be assured of perfect grades. Moreover, your grades will be consistent.

Engineering

Engineering is quite a demanding subject. Students face a lot of pressure and barely have enough time to do what they love to do. Our academic writing service got you covered! Our engineering specialists follow the paper instructions and ensure timely delivery of the paper.

Nursing

In the nursing course, you may have difficulties with literature reviews, annotated bibliographies, critical essays, and other assignments. Our nursing assignment writers will offer you professional nursing paper help at low prices.

Sociology

Truth be told, sociology papers can be quite exhausting. Our academic writing service relieves you of fatigue, pressure, and stress. You can relax and have peace of mind as our academic writers handle your sociology assignment.

Business

We take pride in having some of the best business writers in the industry. Our business writers have a lot of experience in the field. They are reliable, and you can be assured of a high-grade paper. They are able to handle business papers of any subject, length, deadline, and difficulty!

Statistics

We boast of having some of the most experienced statistics experts in the industry. Our statistics experts have diverse skills, expertise, and knowledge to handle any kind of assignment. They have access to all kinds of software to get your assignment done.

Law

Writing a law essay may prove to be an insurmountable obstacle, especially when you need to know the peculiarities of the legislative framework. Take advantage of our top-notch law specialists and get superb grades and 100% satisfaction.

What discipline/subjects do you deal in?

We have highlighted some of the most popular subjects we handle above. Those are just a tip of the iceberg. We deal in all academic disciplines since our writers are as diverse. They have been drawn from across all disciplines, and orders are assigned to those writers believed to be the best in the field. In a nutshell, there is no task we cannot handle; all you need to do is place your order with us. As long as your instructions are clear, just trust we shall deliver irrespective of the discipline.

Are your writers competent enough to handle my paper?

Our essay writers are graduates with bachelor's, masters, Ph.D., and doctorate degrees in various subjects. The minimum requirement to be an essay writer with our essay writing service is to have a college degree. All our academic writers have a minimum of two years of academic writing. We have a stringent recruitment process to ensure that we get only the most competent essay writers in the industry. We also ensure that the writers are handsomely compensated for their value. The majority of our writers are native English speakers. As such, the fluency of language and grammar is impeccable.

What if I don’t like the paper?

There is a very low likelihood that you won’t like the paper.

Reasons being:

  • When assigning your order, we match the paper’s discipline with the writer’s field/specialization. Since all our writers are graduates, we match the paper’s subject with the field the writer studied. For instance, if it’s a nursing paper, only a nursing graduate and writer will handle it. Furthermore, all our writers have academic writing experience and top-notch research skills.
  • We have a quality assurance that reviews the paper before it gets to you. As such, we ensure that you get a paper that meets the required standard and will most definitely make the grade.

In the event that you don’t like your paper:

  • The writer will revise the paper up to your pleasing. You have unlimited revisions. You simply need to highlight what specifically you don’t like about the paper, and the writer will make the amendments. The paper will be revised until you are satisfied. Revisions are free of charge
  • We will have a different writer write the paper from scratch.
  • Last resort, if the above does not work, we will refund your money.

Will the professor find out I didn’t write the paper myself?

Not at all. All papers are written from scratch. There is no way your tutor or instructor will realize that you did not write the paper yourself. In fact, we recommend using our assignment help services for consistent results.

What if the paper is plagiarized?

We check all papers for plagiarism before we submit them. We use powerful plagiarism checking software such as SafeAssign, LopesWrite, and Turnitin. We also upload the plagiarism report so that you can review it. We understand that plagiarism is academic suicide. We would not take the risk of submitting plagiarized work and jeopardize your academic journey. Furthermore, we do not sell or use prewritten papers, and each paper is written from scratch.

When will I get my paper?

You determine when you get the paper by setting the deadline when placing the order. All papers are delivered within the deadline. We are well aware that we operate in a time-sensitive industry. As such, we have laid out strategies to ensure that the client receives the paper on time and they never miss the deadline. We understand that papers that are submitted late have some points deducted. We do not want you to miss any points due to late submission. We work on beating deadlines by huge margins in order to ensure that you have ample time to review the paper before you submit it.

Will anyone find out that I used your services?

We have a privacy and confidentiality policy that guides our work. We NEVER share any customer information with third parties. Noone will ever know that you used our assignment help services. It’s only between you and us. We are bound by our policies to protect the customer’s identity and information. All your information, such as your names, phone number, email, order information, and so on, are protected. We have robust security systems that ensure that your data is protected. Hacking our systems is close to impossible, and it has never happened.

How our Assignment  Help Service Works

1.      Place an order

You fill all the paper instructions in the order form. Make sure you include all the helpful materials so that our academic writers can deliver the perfect paper. It will also help to eliminate unnecessary revisions.

2.      Pay for the order

Proceed to pay for the paper so that it can be assigned to one of our expert academic writers. The paper subject is matched with the writer’s area of specialization.

3.      Track the progress

You communicate with the writer and know about the progress of the paper. The client can ask the writer for drafts of the paper. The client can upload extra material and include additional instructions from the lecturer. Receive a paper.

4.      Download the paper

The paper is sent to your email and uploaded to your personal account. You also get a plagiarism report attached to your paper.

smile and order essaysmile and order essay PLACE THIS ORDER OR A SIMILAR ORDER WITH US TODAY AND GET A PERFECT SCORE!!!

order custom essay paper